Chad Meister’s Evil: A Guide for the Perplexed is a remarkably concise and accessible introduction to the “problem of evil”. Meister summarises a quarter century of academic debate and philosophical reflection in a book that can be read in an evening. He also finds time to critique Hindu and Buddhist responses to evil, and to present a moral argument for Christianity based on the gravity of evil and suffering.
Mesiter leads with the logical problem of evil, which was presented most effectively by JL Mackie.
i) A wholly good being always eliminates evil as far as it can.
ii) There are no limits to what an omnipotent and omniscient being can do.
iii) So, if a wholly good, omnipotent and omniscient being exists, it eliminates evil completely.
iv) Evil has not been eliminated completely.
v) Thus, a wholly good, omnipotent and omniscient being does not exist.
So far, so reasonable. However, Alvin Plantinga provided a significant rebuttal to this argument with a free will defence which questioned premise (ii). There are limits on omnipotence; to create beings capable of achieving virtue God must give those beings the gift of free-will. An omnipotent God cannot force a free being to choose the good. So if God created beings with free will – be they humans or angelic powers – omnipotence could not prevent them from freely choosing evil.
Plantinga’s defence attributes earthquakes and famines to fallen angels; this seems a little implausible, to say the least. But a defence need not be plausible to be successful; remember, Mackie claimed that the existence of God and the presence of evil are logically incompatible. To rebut this charge the theist need only show that they do not entail a contradiction; any consistent scenario that reconciles the two propositions demonstrates that the “logical problem of evil” fails.
So it is widely accepted that the logical problem of evil has been answered. However, William Rowe has articulated an evidential problem of evil, which claims that a good, omnipotent and omniscient creator would eliminate every purposeless or gratuitous evil. Yet there are so many instances of intense suffering it is probable that at least one could have been prevented without losing some greater good. Therefore it is probable that God does not exist.
Meister counters that absence of evidence of a divine purpose is not evidence of absence. Humans have limitations that might prevent them from knowing all the goods that God is aware of. This is Stephen Wykstra’s famous “noseeum” defence. Consider insects so small that they are invisible to the naked human eye. If an entomologist were to tell you that your arm was covered in such insects, it would not be rational to deny this because you cannot see any insects. You are not in an epistemic position to detect these creatures with your eyes.
Similarly, consider the gap between God’s mind and ours. Meister argues that the gap is so great that God might have knowledge of values that we cannot detect. We cannot detect any good that would realised by certain instances of intense suffering. However it would be false to infer that no goods are realised by these instances of intense suffering. We are not in an epistemic position to detect all the goods that God knows of. Horrific evils might be necessary to bring about these greater goods.
However, I believe that there are dangers in leaning too heavily on this defence. As Meister acknowledges, if God knows of values that we cannot even conceive of, we cannot rule out goods that would justify God in permitting any amount of evil whatever. So, if human life was nothing more than a seemingly endless series of intense pains and emotional traumas we would not infer that there was good evidence that God did not exist. It would always be possible, given the gap between our mind and the divine mind that God could know of values that would justify even infinite suffering!
Furthermore, if no amount of suffering or dysteleology can count as evidence against God, it is difficult to see what could count as evidence for God’ existence. Theists often argue that there are contingent and valuable states of affairs – life, for example - that are best accounted for by God because God has the power and motivation to bring them about. If we concede that our grasp of what God values is very limited, then we have few grounds to claim that we know what God would desire to bring about. Design arguments could be undermined on this point.
It seems better, then, to challenge Rowe’s assumption that God must not create a world in which individuals undergo gratuitous evils. God created a world in which horrendous evils were possible; if he had not, we would have lost the great good of free will. In a world with free-will, gratuitous evils are inevitable. Yet suppose God ensures that anyone who desires a life with vastly more good than evil can have a life that contains vastly more good than evil. In that case, why could God not allow a world which contains instances of gratuitous suffering? Of course God would need an afterlife to provide goods which would overwhelm experiences of suffering. But Meister advances several arguments to show that belief in an afterlife is quite reasonable.
While we cannot imagine the greatness of heaven or the New Creation, we know that they will surpass our wildest expectations. Arguably, we can conceive of goods that would render the “noseeum” defence redundant. In his last chapter, Meister deals with horrendous evils. These are instances of suffering that seem to render a human life worthless; a person enduring such suffering could rationally claim “it would have been better that I had not been born.” Yet draws on Simone Weil and Marilyn McCord Adams, and points out that there are eternal goods which can overwhelm and redeem the most horrendous events.
The torture and murder of the innocent Son of God would seem to be a paradigm case of a gratuitous, horrendous evil. Yet, even after Jesus cried out to the Father who had seemingly forsaken him, he surrendered fully to his Father, placing his life into his hands. “In affliction,” argues Meister “we are at once both at the greatest distance from God but potentially as close as possible. The choice is ours – whether we receive the invitation of closeness, and so receive the amazing goods offered by God, or reject that invitation and so experience hell on earth.”
Furthermore, suffering can allow us to identify with Christ, who endured horrendous evils and suffering. And the experience of redemption will be all the sweeter for those who have endured the darkest exile. Intimacy with God is not a secular good, but a sacred and eternal value. It might not be a good that Rowe recognises, but it is certainly one that we can conceive of. It is also possible that some experiences of divine healing would not be possible without the existence of seemingly random and horrendous evils. The theist has good defences against the evidential problem of evil. Can we go further, and provide a complete and convincing explanation for evil?
Theodicies are rather different beasts than defences. A theodicy attempts to vindicate the ways of God in the world by providing a plausible explanation for the presence of evil. “Free-will theodicies” attribute the presence of evil to the human decision to rebel against God. Natural evil is, in part, the divine response to human sin. Meister rejects this response because science demonstrates that natural evil predated humans by millions of years. This is thin ground, to my mind, for rejecting a free-will theodicy. It is specifically human suffering - not animal suffering - that a good theodicy seeks to answer. Over-educated urbanites might get themselves into a rage over the suffering of Bambi and his mother. But I do not see that Big Macs demand a theodicy.
It is entirely possible that that close fellowship with God would have allowed humans to avoid natural evils, or to experience miraculous healing if they were encountered. When humans broke free from God they lost these resources. Or perhaps God would have created the New Heavens and New Earth if the first humans had remained obedient. Once they rebelled, God put eschatology “on hold” until he had brought the human race back to order. So the Augustinian theodicy retains its coherence. How does it compare to Meister’s preferred “soul building” theodicy, which argues that humans were born to suffer, so that we could learn courage and compassion?
No doubt humans can learn these virtues in a fallen world; perhaps this partly explains why God allows us to live in one. But when we encounter evil, we instinctively feel that this is not how the world was meant to be. Evil is scandalous; I am not sure that “soul building” theodicies can adequately account for that fact. It seems more likely that we are suffering the consequences of a fall; we have broken fellowship with a God of limitless love and power. In any case, evil is so chaotic and irrational, that I am not sure that we will ever develop a theodicy that will be entirely persuasive. The church will simply have to settle for good defences and offer good reasons to trust God when the darkness seems overwhelming.
My disagreements with Meister should not be read as criticism of his book; it is wonderful that such a thin volume could provide so much substance for debate and reflection. Meister has provided students, teachers and pastors with a robust response to some of the deepest questions that a human can ask. Why do I suffer? What can I do about it? Is there any help? Can I dare to hope?
Apologetics 315 Book Reviewer Graham Veale is Head of Religious Education at City of Armagh High School. With David Glass, he runs the apologetics group Saints and Sceptics. Their articles can be read at www.saintsandsceptics.org
Saturday, January 26, 2013
2nd Book Review: Evil: A Guide for the Perplexed
Topics:
apologetics
,
Book Reviews
,
Chad Meister
,
Philosophy
,
Problem of Evil
Blog Archive
-
▼
2013
(376)
-
▼
January
(36)
- Free: Essential Apologetics PowerPoint Series
- SALT Conference Videos Free Online
- Terminology Tuesday: The Five Ways
- Apologist Interview: John Bloom
- John Elder on Archaeology and the Bible
- 2nd Book Review: Evil: A Guide for the Perplexed
- Review: Evil: A Guide for the Perplexed by Chad Me...
- Weekly Apologetics Bonus Links (01/18 - 01/25)
- Petition: Churches for Apologetics
- Michael Licona Interview Transcript
- God & Arguments from Morality
- Terminology Tuesday: Middle Knowledge
- Tactical Faith Interview: Matthew Burford
- Ravi Zacharias on the Problem of Evil
- Book Review: The Bible Among the Myths by John Oswalt
- Weekly Apologetics Bonus Links (01/11 - 01/18)
- SALT Apologetics Conference January 19th & 20th
- Old Testament & the New Atheists: Peter J. Williams
- Scott Klusendorf Interview Transcript
- Terminology Tuesday: Naturalism, Natural Theology
- Apologist Interview: Frank Turek
- William Lane Craig on Apologetics Training
- Book Review: Defending the Faith: Apologetics in W...
- Weekly Apologetics Bonus Links (01/04 - 01/11)
- Free Logic Primer eBook Download
- Best Selling Apologetics Books of 2012
- Michael Patton Interview Transcript
- Terminology Tuesday: Occam's Razor
- Apologist Interview: J. Warner Wallace
- J. Budziszewski on Agnosticism
- Book Review: Cold-Case Christianity by J. Warner W...
- Weekly Apologetics Bonus Links (12/28 - 01/04)
- Interview Transcript: David Instone-Brewer
- Featured Resource: The Logic Classroom
- Michael Licona on Bible Contradictions (MP3)
- Terminology Tuesday: Transcendence
-
▼
January
(36)
4 comments :
The free will theodicy is itself thin ground in my opinion. And not just because it doesn't account for animal suffering or natural evils.
First, it's premised on a controversial view of free will. The only reason most people, like William Lane Craig, are able to get away with it in debates is because the person they are debating and the audience usually operates on nothing more than a "folk intuition" of the term "free will." But as studies have shown, this folk intuition is overall a shallow and contradictory notion of free will (e.g., Shaun Nichols, Folk Intuitions on Free Will, in the Journal of Cognition and Culture).
Second, it's premised on the controversial view that free will is worth the price of the evils. Not everyone agrees with that premise, as Dostoevsky explores in The Brothers Karamazov.
Third, applied to God, it just doesn't match up with how we respond to evils from our fellow "free will" creatures. If I have a son I truly love, I'm not going to let him exercise his free will to destroy his life on drugs. Or if I have a daughter I love, I'm not going to let the man down the street exercise his free will to rape and mutilate my daughter.
Aside from that, many people do think animal suffering demands a theodicy. The majority of people may not think a Big Mac needs a theodicy, unless you tell them the cow was tortured needlessly prior to being put out of its misery and becoming a Big Mac. Then I'm willing to bet that the majority of people *will* think "Big Macs" demands a theodicy.
And as an off-topic note: Mr. (Dr?) Veale says "It is entirely possible that that close fellowship with God would have allowed humans to avoid natural evils, or to experience miraculous healing if they were encountered."
OEC usually scoff at such a scenario under a YEC scheme. What's sauce for the goose...
Hi Jonathan,
1) I am not at all convinced that concepts of indeterministic free-will depend on"folk intuitions"; and you'll need to build a thorough case (that deals with Van Inwagen's work, for example, or Timothy 'Connor's, or EJ Lowe's) to show that they should be rejected.
2) It is not clear that God has the duties, or the role, of a human parent. We can stretch that analogy too far in my opinion.
3) I am not at all convinced that any theodicy will be entirely convincing. I note this at the end of the review.
4) I mentioned "eternal goods". Free-will is not worth the price of the evil from a secular perspective; but as powerful as his rhetoric is, Dostoevsky did not close the debate. it is not clear what the "price of the evils" is too high from an eternal perspective!
4) I've don't recall scoffing at YECs recently....anyway this possibility has been offered by Peter van Inwagen, is consistent with the Kingdom of God in the Gospels.
"IVAN: I don't want the mother to embrace the oppressor who threw her son to the dogs! She dare not forgive him! Let her forgive him for herself, if she will, let her forgive the torturer for the immeasurable suffering of her mother's heart. But the sufferings of her tortured child she has no right to forgive; she dare not forgive the torturer, even if the child were to forgive him!"
ALYOSHA:" ...you said just now is there a being in the whole world who would have the right to forgive and could forgive? But there is a Being and He can forgive everything, all and for all, because He gave His innocent blood for all and everything. You have forgotten Him, and on Him is built the edifice, and it is to Him they cry aloud, 'Thou art just, O Lord, for Thy ways are revealed!'"
Thanks for the response.
1) I didn't claim (or intend to) that indeterministic concepts of free will are based on folk intuitions. Only that (a) folk intuitions of free will are what most people are operating with and (b) this folk intuition is often shallow and contradictory. The point being that Because people often lack a clear and consistent idea of "free will" and the complex issues involved, it allows the free will defense to have more force or sound more plausible than it would otherwise.
Aside from that, the arguments set forth by Van Inwagen (e.g., the consequence argument) and other libertarians have been vigorously debated in the philosophical literature. This is why I said the free will defense itself seems to be on thin ground
2) In the end, I agree. But a lot more could be said here (e.g., the Bible uses parental language to describe God's love and relationship; sometimes libertarians appeal to such human categories in their discussion of FW, so why rule it out when the tables are turned on them, etc.) that I'll leave alone.
3) I agree that no single theodicy (or even group of theodicies) will be entirely convincing.
4) I'd have to see the eternal goods thing spelled out more. (Though I'm not asking you to do so in this context.)
5) I didn't mean the scoffing remark to be directed at anything you've done. It was just a general observation.
Thanks Jonathan
I don't think we'll ever see the free-will debate resolved to everyone's satisfaction. I don't think that this leaves the free-will defence in trouble - the concepts seem clear enough. However, the debate might leave some theodicies (because theodicies try to explain evil) weaker than many think.
Graham
Post a Comment
Thanks for taking the time to comment. By posting your comment you are agreeing to the comment policy.